@LostInParadise “My understanding of Kant is that he believed acts are right or wrong irrespective of their consequences.”
Indeed. Kant was a supporter of the Latin proverb fiat iustitia, pereat mundus (which means “do what is right though the world should perish”). Even though Kant’s first formulation of the categorical imperative (the formulation of universal law) asks us to think about what the world would be like if everyone did what we are thinking about doing, we are supposed to be looking for logical contradictions rather than negative consequences.
“Following Kant, a German family harboring Jews during WW II would have been obligated to inform on them if asked about their whereabouts by an SS officer.”
As it turns out, this does not actually follow from Kant’s views. To lie is to make a statement that one believes to be false with the intention of making someone believe the false statement. Since lying requires one to make a statement, one could just stay silent. And since lying also requires us to believe that what we say is false, we could attempt a misleading truth (as there is no such thing as a lie of omission on Kant’s view).
Therefore, the duty not to lie does not entail a duty to tell the truth. We do not have to inform on innocent people, and we can even say things like “I saw them traveling south down this very road last week. I think they were trying to escape you!” You just happen to leave out that the journey ended at your front door. The officer may end up deceived, but not by you. Rather, he is deceived by his own mistaken assumptions.
Lest this seem like getting off on some ad hoc technicality, let us look at a different example that Kant gives in his Lectures on Ethics. There he discusses an attempt to catch a thief by packing one’s bags (as if preparing to leave one’s house) and then waiting for the criminal to break in. Packing one’s bags typically indicates that one is going on a journey, but it is no way a statement or assertion of such an intention. It’s just a sign in the sense of an action that typically accompanies such an intention.
@LuckyGuy In cases A, B, and C, Kant would say that the action is morally neutral. Obviously, it is not morally wrong to do the good deed, but the actions are not morally good because they are not done from the motive of duty. Case D is a bit trickier. If the person sees the need and says “someone has to do it, and it might as well be me,” then they very well may be acting out of duty.
Consider a similar case: if a man is having a heart attack in the middle of a crowd, someone ought to call for help. Yet we cannot say that any particular person has more of a duty to do so than any other one. If I’m in the crowd and already have my cell phone out, I might shout “I’m calling 911 right now!” to let everyone know that the situation is being handled. It’s easy for me to do, but I’m not doing it just for fun. If my response is generated by a sense of duty (because someone has to do it, and I can do it easily), then the action would count as morally good/praiseworthy on Kant’s view. The ease doesn’t undermine the goodness.
Let me know if this didn’t fully answer the question, though.
@dopeguru “if everybody did an action that had a good result, like helping an old woman, out of selfish reasons, then nobody would find “helping” to be an act that is good. So it would actually be bad, if everyone did it with negative motives.”
Well, we wouldn’t want to live in such a world. But that doesn’t mean that helping out of selfish motives would be morally bad. It might just tell us that we sometimes need to help others for non-selfish reasons. Kant actually addresses this with his distinction between perfect and imperfect duties. Perfect duties are “always on.” They are the things that we must always do or never do (these being ultimately the same thing: a duty to never murder is the same as a duty to always refrain from murdering). Imperfect duties are things that we have to do, but not on every occasion. So it might be wrong for us to never donate to charity, but we don’t have to donate every time we have the opportunity.
How might we distinguish between perfect and imperfect duties? According to Kant, we can use the formulation of universal law (“act only according to that maxim whereby you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law without contradiction”). The issue is what sort of contradiction we run into. A world in which everyone breaks their promises, for example, is said to be impossible because the institution of promising relies on some people keeping their word. If everyone broke their promises all the time, there would be no institution of promising for the promise breakers to exploit in the first place. Since this world is impossible, our duty to keep promises is perfect.
But not all contradictions are logical contradictions (i.e., impossibilities). Sometimes they are practical contradictions. These are contradictions in our will: we cannot consistently do something while also willing it to be the case that everyone acts the same way. Universal selfishness is supposed to be like this, according to Kant. It is not impossible that a world should exist where everyone acted selfishly all the time. But we cannot consistently will that this be the case because our selfishness is best served by the altruism of others. That is to say, a selfish person ought to want a world in which others are not selfish. This is inconsistent with universalizing our (proposed) selfishness, however, so there is a practical contradiction here. Thus we have an imperfect duty to sometimes act unselfishly.
“So it makes me think someone who acts out of selfishness but achieves something good GOES AGAINST the universal law rule because nobody would find that action good anymore.”
This is why Kant doesn’t think we ought to evaluate actions on their own. We evaluate them along with their motives (that is, the maxims of our actions—our reason for doing them). A useful example here might be cutting someone open with a knife. It’s terrible when a criminal does it to rob and/or kill you, but it’s great when a doctor does it to save your life. Evaluating the action in isolation is no good. We have to understand the motive, too. So Kant would say that you shouldn’t think of the selfish action just in terms of the action, but in terms of the action/maxim pair. We go wrong if we stop thinking of the action as good just because we don’t think it is good when done selfishly.
“Kant says before you act think of what would happen if everyone acted that way… That confuses me.”
Well, “what if everyone did that?” is more a slogan used to help people understand the formulation of universal law and not anything Kant actually said himself. I agree that it is confusing insofar as it tempts people to think of Kant in consequentialist terms. What the slogan is supposed to mean, though, is just what I have explained above: consider what the world would be like if everyone acted on a particular action/maxim pair at every opportunity. If that world is impossible or if there is an inconsistency between willing the action for oneself and willing it for everyone, then it’s wrong (according to Kant). It’s not about consequences, but logic.